Hill's Elements of Philosophy
Hill's Elements of Philosophy
An anonymous writer in the Boston Pilot assails with great
bitterness and some personal abuse, both of which are very
unphilosophical, and neither of which is of any logical value,
our criticism, in our number for April last, of Professor Hill's
much-praised " Elements of Philosophy." The anonymous
writer we find partially indorsed, much to our surprise, by
our friend of The Louisville Catholic Advocate, for whose
able and independent editor we have a very high esteem.
The anonymous writer in the Boston Pilot attacks us with
great vehemence, and writes with an imposing self-assurance,
which may lead some readers to imagine that he really
understands something of the subject on which he writes.
We shall not attempt to prove the contrary, for we cannot so
far derogate from the dignity of a quarterly review as to
reply to an anonymous scribbler in a weekly newspaper,
and especially a newspaper of such a character as the Boston
Pilot.
There is one charge the writer makes, since it is repeated
by our friend of the Catholic Advocate, and indorsed, we are
informed, by Father Hill himself, if, indeed, it did not originate
with him, that we feel bound to notice. It is that we do not
know Latin, or at least are too ignorant of Latin to under-
stand the technicalities of St. Thomas and the scholastic
philosophy. We have never pretended to be a classical
scholar, nor a thorough Latinist. Yet we do claim to have
enough acquaintance with the Latin of the medieval scholas-
tics, to read and understand them, as well as some understand-
ing of their technicalities both in philosophy and theology.
But suppose we have not. Does not Fr. Hill write his
philosophy in English for students whose mother-tongue is
English, and will it be alleged that we are too ignorant of
Latin to understand English? Is it necessary to charge us
with ignorance of Latin in order to prove that we misunder-
stand or cannot understand Fr. Hill's English? This
would only confirm the criticism made in our first notice of
his work, that his English is unintelligible to a reader who
is ignorant of the scholastic philosophy and of the Latin.
Indeed it is a grave objection to the work, as an English
work, that it is not intelligible to a simple English reader
who knows no language but his own. The attempt to make
out that our criticisms must be unfounded because we are
ignorant of Latin, only justifies our criticism.
We regard Fr. Hill as a man of passable ability, and
as possessing considerable philosophical erudition, but he is
bound by obedience to maintain prescribed system of
philosophy, and he is not free to exercise any philosophical
insight or originality of his own if he possesses any. At
best he can only tell us what others have said, only gyrate in
the circle prescribed by the general of his order. We admit
the right of the Church to condemn us if in philosophy or
any of the sciences we emit a false or an erroneous proposi-
tion; but we have yet to learn that we are bound as a
Catholic to accept, with the reverence and submission due to
a dogma of faith, every philosophic proposition to be found
in Suarez, or even St. Thomas. Philosophy is a rational
science, and is not , like faith, to be taught by authority; and
we tell the philosophers of the illustrious Society of Jesus,
that their recent attempts to make philosophy an authoritative
as distinguished from a rational science, are ill-advised, and
destructive of human reason itself. Their general commands
them to return to Aristotle and Fonseca, that is, to the
dominant philosophy of the early part of the seventeenth
century. Do you know the history of philosophy since?
Starting in the seventeenth century with the philosophy
to which your professors are commanded by your general to
return, philosophy soon with Descartes lost its objectivity,
and became purely subjective; and in the following century
with the Abbe Condillac and others it lost the subject, and
resulted, as with Hegel, in pure nihilism. What better result
can be expected from persisting in teaching in our schools
the same philosophy? It must from the first have contained
the germs, if I may so say, of the nihilism in which we
have seen it result: and what is to hinder if from terminating
in the same result again, if insisted on? You cannot, do
what you will, reason as illogically as you please, prevent
society in the long run from drawing from the premises you
give it, their strictly logical consequences, unless those conse-
quences should happen to be favorable to truth and holiness.
We do not pretend that Fr. Hill does not assert the
reality both of the object and the subject; but, if we under-
stand it, his system recognizes of admits no principle or
premises from which that reality follows as an inevitable
consequence. I have wholly mistaken the rev. professor,
if he anywhere asserts the identity of the principles of
science and the principles of things: that is, only the real is
an object of science, and the unreal, which is nothing, is
unintelligible, unthinkable. The system he defends, holds
that the unreal,that is, the possible, the abstract, seclusa
the concrete or the power of the real, is not a pure nullity,
but is intelligible,- an object of thought. Thus the author
writes: "Terms, considered in respect to their objects, are
real and logical: of the first and second intention: absolute
and connotative" (relative). The object of the real term
actually exists outside of the mind; it is a real or actual
object, or at least really possible. The really possible is
simply a contradiction in terms. The two terms cannot go
together, are as incompatible, the one with the other, as square
circle, burning cold, or wet drought. Father Koop has clearly
proved in the Review both for April and for July, that the
possible is nothing in itself, therefore always unreal, conse-
quently never in itself the object of a real term. If we
make it, with the rev. professor, an object of thought, we
assume that the unreal is thinkable, that is, that we can
know without knowing anything. Then the principles of
science and the principles of things are not identical. How,
then, know that there is any object actually existing out of
the mind, or that there are things at all? Say we not, then,
truly that, though the professor asserts an objective world,
he is unable, by the system of philosophy he is obliged as a
Jesuit to defend, to prove it. By denying the identity of the
principles of science and the principles of things, that
philosophy concedes that science may be unreal, and, there-
fore, no evidence or proof of the reality of its object.
Fr. Hill asserts ontology as one of the parts of philosophy.
The assertion we accept, but we find in his philosophy no
principle recognized that warrants it. We do not find in his
" Elements" any solution, nor, indeed, any consideration of
the problem: How pass from the psychological to the onto-
logical, from the subjective to the objective, the real pons
asinorum of modern philosophers? The professor does not
seem to be aware that there is and can be no passage for
the human mind from the one to the other. Suppose the
mind has, as Pere Martin, Fr. Rothenflue, and the Louvain
professors teach, immediate perception of ens or being, and
that ens or being is God, you cannot conclude from the
perception or intuition of God, if we have it, the existence of
the soul; for that would imply that creation of contingent
existences is necessay: which is a contradiction in terms,
since it makes contingent existence necessary and not contin-
gent, and asserts pure pantheism. If you conclude the
ontological from the psychological, God from the soul, you
make God the necessary product of the soul, or assert the
Egoism of Fichte. But waiving this, if the soul can think,
that is, know, in any instance, without thinking or knowing,
any object really, actually existing out or independent of
itself, as it must if it can know possibles or abstractions, by
what possible process can it prove that there is anything
actually existing outside of itself?
We are assumed to be ignorant of Latin, are assumed, as a
matter of course, not to be able to understand Fr, Hill writing
in English! We are told that we charge him ignorantly and
falsely when we call him a conceptualist. We are told that
we seem not to know the scholastic distinction between the
first and the second intention, or at least to pay no attention
to it. We paid no attention to it, we own, because the dis-
tinction had no bearing on the points we were discussing,
and could not relieve Fr.Hill's philosophy of the objections
we felt it our duty to urgy against it. The distinction as-
serted by the author, expressed in plain English, we take it,
is the distinction between intuition and reflection, or between
thinking and rethinking: the pensare and the ripensare of
the Italians. Thus the author writes, p. 20 : "A term of
the first intention expresses the object seen by the first and
direct act of the mind, in which the object is affirmed with its
real predicates; a term of the second intention stands for
another concept, which the mind forms by a second and reflex
act, in which second act logical or universal predicates are
attributed: v. g., the terms genus, species, universals, are
terms of the second intention, because their objects are not
real, but logical only; " that is, formed by the reflex act of
the mind, that is, abstractions, creatures of reflection, there-
fore unreal, simple nullities. Does not this bear out our
charge, that Fr. Hill in his philosophy is " a conceptualist, if
not a nominalist" ? We are examining, not his intentions,
but the philosophical principles asserted or implied in his
definitions.
Now, what was the question debated between the medieval
realists on the one side, and the conceptualists and nominalists
on the other? The question was confined to universals
including genera and species. The realists, represented by
Guillaume de Champeaux, of St. Victor, Paris, maintained
that they are real; the conceptualists, represented by the Bas-
Breton, Abelard, maintained against him that they are not
indeed mere words as asserted by the nominalists, represented
by Roscelin, another Bas-Breton, but conceptions formed by
the mind, and without any actual existence out of it: the precise
doctrine of Fr. Hill. St. Thomas teaches that universals
exist in conceptu, or in mente, cum fundamento in re; which is
true of abstractions, such as whiteness, redness, roundness,
hardness, etc., but it is not of genera and species, which are
terms not of the second, but of the first intention, to adopt the
very un- English terminology of Professor Hill. As to the
objective reality of genera and species, it makes no difference
whether you call them mental conceptions with Abelard, or
empty words with Roscelin; for, if you deny their objective
reality, you can assert only a verbal or a subjective difference
between an oak and a pine, a man and a horse. We do not
doubt the intentions of the author or the justness of his views,
when he forgets his system and follows his common-sense.
But the first intention being only an act, a direct and
immediate act, if you will, of the mind, gives only a concept;
and the author concedes it, when he says the mind in its reflex
act, or act of the second intention, forms another concept:
which plainly implies that the object affirmed in the first
intention is a concept. It will be no answer to this to say
that, though the object of the term is a concept, the object
of the mental act is a real object, existing out of the mind
and independent of it; for, if the term stands for a concept,
and not for the real object, it is inappropriate and false.
Moreover, if the term expresses a concept only, and not the
real object, we have our old difficulty, How know that there
is a real object out of the mind, of which the term expresses
the cencept, and which responds to it? The direct act
of the mind is never, taken by itself, anything but a concept,
and every concept is subjective. How pass from it to the
objective, or prove that in the concept, or idea, any object
but the idea or concept, which is in the mind, is apprehended?
The idea or concept, if we understand the author, stands in
his terminology for the species impressa and the species ex-
pressa of the schoolmen; but he derivers the species from the
direct act of the subject, while St. Thomas and all the
medieval scholastics we are acquainted with, derive it
from the object. They teach, as does Plato, that we know
only per ideam, per imaginem, or, as St. Thomas says, per
similitudinem, which is the representation-presentation, as
we prefer to say, for representation is a term of the second
intention-of the object to the mind, not formed by its own
act, direct or indirect, simply because without it the mind
cannot act at all, does not even actually exist, and is only
in potentia ad actum.
We objected to Fr. Hill that he makes the mind an in-
dependent intelligence, apprehending by its own inherent
activity alone, without the concurrent activity of the object.
This we are told is a misrepresentation-that he holds that
the mind knows only by the concurrent activity of subject
and object. Yet the anonymous critic who accuses us of
misrepresentation, says that the idea, or concept, according
to Fr. Hill, is that in which or by which the mind knows
or apprehends the object: which, as we understand it, is, so
far, the doctrine of St. Thomas, and our own; but Fr.
Hill makes the idea, or concept, the product of the direct act
of the mind, and therefore purely subjective; not as we,
following St. Thomas and the medieval philosophers, do -the
active affirmation to the mind by the object of itself. The
medieval peripatetics make the object supply their phantasms
and species, the idea or similitude by which or in which the
mind apprehends it; and we can see no essential difference
between holding the soul to be an independent intelligence
apprehending the object by its own inherent activity alone,
and holding that the concept, idea, image, or similitude, in
which or by which the object is affirmed or apprehended,
is supplied by the mind or soul itself. The professor's phi-
losophy is in substance only the Kantian, subjectivism; the
germ of which may be found in Leibnitz, who, in his " Remarks
on Locke's 'Essay on the Human Understanding ,' "says
that he holds that " the principal part of our ideas come from
our own resources (nos fonds);" still more decidedly, perhaps,
in his amendment of the peripatetic maxim,Nihil est in in-
tellcetu quod non prius fuerit in sensu, NISI IPSE INTELLECTUS.
To us it seems little less than absurd to say the mind appre-
hends or knows by the concurrent activity of the subject and
the object, and then to maintain that the subject supplies by
its own direct act the concept, idea, image, or similitude, by
which or in which the object is affirmed.
Moreover, the professor, as we have seen, in defining what
he calls a real term, says its object is " a real or actual object,
or, at least, really possibble." The possible is no object
"actually existing outside of the mind," indeed, has no actual
existence at all. What has no actual existence cannot act.
If, then, it can be apprehended by the mind, as the professor
and his school maintain, the subject can know by itself alone
without the concurrent activity of the object, and is therefore
an independent itelligence: as we never represented him and his
school as holding. Of course, we never pretended and do
not pretend that he or his school expressly maintain this, or
would not disavow it; but we maintain that it follows as a
necessary consequence from the principles or premises, as
we here show, which they do expressly assert or maintain.
Fr. Rothenflue has given an admirable refutation of pan-
theism; and yet his philosophy in its principles, as that of
Victor Cousin, is undeniably pantheistic. We must judge
all systems, not by the intentions, or even formal assertains,
of their authors, but by the principles which they maintain.
It is not every philosopher who foresees all the logical con-
sequences that follow from the principles he assumes; and
especially is this true of authors who take their principles
or premises from a school or a great and renowned meta-
physician, without original investigation, or attempting to
verify them for themselves.
We may be permitted to remark that there is, and neces-
sarily must be, a great difference between theology and
philosophy. The theologian proceeds from principles divinely
revealed, and therefore certain. He cannot err as to his
principles or premises, and, if he is able to reason logically,
his conclusions will be true and certain. Hence St. Thomas
calls theology scientia divina. Theologians may, indeed, err
in their deductions, and in respect to the use they make of
elements borrowed from natural reason; but, as their principles
are taken from divine revelation, and have the authority of
the word of God, they are included in the depositum of
faith, watched over and protected by the infallible authority
of the Church. He who proceeds from them as his premises,
and can reason logically, may arrive at authoritaitve con-
clusions. Hence the authority in theology of the great
doctors of the Church, and of the traditional teaching of
Catholic schools; and yet neither this tradition of the schools,
nor the dicta of the doctors are infallible, and are authoritative
only as witnesses to the teaching of the Church. One may
even in theology differ, for good and solid reasons, from an
opinion of St. Ambrose, St. Augustine, St. Basil, St, Gregory
the Great, St. Thomas, or St. Liguori, but it would be
temeraria to do so without such reasons. Fr. Ballerini
differs on the question of Probabilism from St. Liguori, and,
in our judgment, which is worth perhaps nothing, very justly;
for we have no Gunter's rule by which to determine the
different degrees of probability, or what degree of probability
binds the conscience, or what degree leaves it free. An
uncertain law does not bind the conscience; and whether
the law is more or less probable can ,make no difference, for,
whether more or less probable, it is still uncertain. If it is
probable that the law does not forbid this or that act, then the
confessor cannot pronounce me guilty of sin if I perform it.
The question between probabilism and probabiliorism, or
equi-probabilism, is, it seems to us, of little practical impor-
tance, because in practice one must be either a probabilist or a
tutiorist.
If we may say so much in regard to theololgians and
theological schools, we may say even more of philosophers
and philosophical schools; for the principles of philosophy
are not drawn from divine revelation, but from natural
reason, of which no man or set of men enjoy the monopoly.
Great names in philosophy, as Plato, Aristotle, St. Augustine,
St. Thomas, St. Bonaventura, Suarez, Descartes, Malebranche,
John Locke, Hume, Reid, Berkeley, Leibnitz, Cardinal Gerdil,
Kant, Fichte, Cousin, Vico, Rosmini, Galluppi, Gioberti,
may be consulted and should be, not as absolute authorities,
but for their testimony as to what may be presumed to be
the principles and dictates of reason. Their opinions
enlighten our reason, but do not supersede or conclude it.
Great respect is certainly due to the teachings or the
traditional philosophy of our Catholic schools, as it may be
supposed that the professors in these schools would not be
permitted to go on for centuries, under the very eye of the
Church, in teaching an unsound or false system of philosophy
or of science; yet this argument is by no means conclusive,
and has less weight than at first sight it would seem to have.
Professors, however learned and honest, are no more infallible
in questions of human reason, than they are in questions of
faith. The geocentric theory was for centuries taught in
Catholic schools by Catholic professors, who, when the helio-
centric theory was broached, denounced it as heretical and
false. Yet in later times Catholic professors have very
generally rejected the geocentric theory, and it has long since
ceased to be the received doctrine of Catholic schools. The
infallibility of the Church is not pledged to our Catholic
schools, and, in matters of human science, their doctrines, like
those of non-Catholic schools, must stand or fall on their merits
or demerits. If their doctrines impugn or tend directly to
impair faith, the Church reprobates them; but so long as they
remain within the circle of pure human science, she, as a
rule, leaves them free, and intervenes not in the quarrels of
professors.
For four hundred years, or since the so-called Renaissance,
Catholic schools, in spite of the protest of a Savonarola and
others, have cast the minds of the young generations com-
mitted to their charge in a classic, that is, a pagan mould;
and under their influence modern society, even in so-called
Catholic countries, has lapsed into paganism. Who dares
throw the responsibility of the heathenism, evidently revived
and fostered by the schools, on the Church? The basis of the
education given in our schools is heathen, not Christian. Cite,
then, not as authority against us in philosophy or human
science, the traditional teaching of Catholic or of any other
schools, in which the professors, generally speaking, only
follow routine, and repeat the lessons of their predecessors,
often with entire innocence of any investigation or under-
standing of the reasons of what they repeat. The master
says it, and that suffices.
Whether we agree with the schools or not is not the ques-
tion, but is what we defend true, founded on the constituent
principles of natural reason? The critic in the Boston Pilot,
though he accuses us of ignorance of Latin, whence it is
inferred we are incapable of understanding a work on philo-
sophy written in English, never, so far as we have observed,
even attempts to prove that our own philosophy is unsound,
but bends all his rare powers to convicting us of misunder-
standing and misrepresenting Professor Hill, and in proving
that, on the points we objected to, he and his school hold
with us. If so, as the professor writes in English, it is a
little singular that we never discovered it. But we must
say this in our excuse, that, though we find no difficulty
in understanding the author when he explains his meaning
in Latin, which we are said to be ignorant of, we have no little
difficulty in getting at his meaning when he expresses it
in English,- a language of which we have been thought to
know something. Indeed, Fr. Hill's English is far less
intelligible to us than any scholastic Latin we have ever
encountered; and his technology would be absolutely unintel-
ligible to us but for the little acquaintance we have with the
Latin scholastics. We hope the professor will not take it ill,
if, while we do not doubt his proficiency either as an English
or as a Latin scholar, we do not find him very happy in his
rendering of the Latin, in which he studied his philosophy,
into English. When we translate the scholastic technical
terms into English, and conform them to the genius of our
mother-tongue, we suspect he and his defenders fail to recog-
nize them. The author's terminology is un-English, " done
out of Latin," if you will, but " into no language." Take
what he calls terms of the first and second intention: they
have in English, either etymologically or by good usage, no
such meaning as he gives them, but really a very different
meaning, and one that has no analogy to it. We define,
sometimes restrict or enlarge, the meaning of a term to make
it conform to its etymology, but never use a term in a sense
authorized neither by etymology nor good usage, and we try
always, in our use of a term, to retain some trace, at least, of
its primary sense and original figure or symbolism.
But to return to our proper subject. We charged the
professor and his school with maintaining that the soul is an
independent intelligence, which, though pronounced false,
we have seen to be true; for they hold that possibles, as
such, that is, as having no actual existence, are thinkable or
intelligible. we also objected that the system the professor
defends, makes the act of knowledge independent of the
divine creative act, or as we said, the divine concurrence- as
theologians say, the divine concursus. This, we are told, is
a gross and unpardonable misrepresentation, for neither Pro-
fessor Hill, nor any philosopher of his school, ever dreamed of
denying the divine concurrence. Perhaps not, in their sense;
but we doubt if one among them even admits if in the sense
in which the objection assumes that they deny it. As the
point, in our estimation at least, is very important, we must
be allowed to dwell on it for a moment. Every Catholic
theologian, of course, teaches that God is universal Creator,
and efficaciously present at all times and places in all his
works; that all his creatures are absolutely dependent on him
for life, breath, and all things; and that, without his creative
act, they never would and never could have existed. This is
all very well, so far; but, if we mistake not, the school to
which, we take it, the professor belongs, holds that the divine
concurrence in the fact of intelligence is sloely as causa
eminens. It holds that the light of reason is a created light,
not the divine light itself "that enlighteneth every man
coming into this world." Then, as we understand the school,
though the idea is not formed without an object real of pos-
sible outside of the mind, it is the mind by its own activity alone
that forms it: and hence the professor calls it a concept. The
object is passive, and its existence is affirmed by the subject,
and intuition is the act of the subject, and stands opposed to
discursion or ratiocination. The judgment, the object is, or
exists, is affirmed by the mind, not by the object affirming or
presenting itself to the mind, and, by so doing, creating and
constituting the mind, or the soul intelligent.
The school, as we have learned it, holds that mind cog-
nizes creatures, contingent existences, by its own activity,
and in themselves as if they were intelligible in themselves.
The professor evidently so holds; and, though he doubtless
holds that the contingent cannot exist without the creative
act of the necessary, he holds that the contingent can be
known without intuition of the necessary. Here we touch
what we consider the fundamental error of the philosophy
contained in the text-books at present used in all our colleges.
We hold it indubitable that what is not is not intelligible,
is and can be no object of thought or knowledge. Hence we
maintain that being, real and necessary being, ens necessarium
et reale, is alone intelligible per se, as it alone exists per se.
Contingents, creatures, exist only by being, not in, by, or
from themselves, and therefore not cognizable in or by them-
selves, but are intelligible or cognizable only in and by being.
To maintain the contrary is to maintain that what is not,- that
is, what is nothing, a simple nullity,-is intelligible, since,
without real and necessary being, contingents are nothing.
As only what is or exists is intelligible or cognizable, things
are and can be known, if known at all, only as they are, not
as they are not. Hence we maintain that the principles of
science and the principles of things are indentical. Nothing
can be true in the order of science that is not true in the
otder of being. This the philosophy the professor defends,
and which our colleges teach to our ingenuous youth, denies.
It makes the principles of science and the principles of things
different, and therefore holds that the unreal, the non-existent,
can be an object of science: as any one may see who will
read a chapter or two in the Metaphysics of Suarez, one of the
most eminent philosophers and thelologians of the illustrious
Society of Jesus.
Here we may see wherefore the peripateticism of the seven-
teenth century ended, as we have said, in the nihilism of the
Hegelians. Noble and powerful minds expounded, developed,
and defended it, but nothing could save it, for it denied or
failed to assert the identity, we say not of science and things,
but that the Principles of science and the principles of things
are identical, that science must follow the order of being, for
only that which is, only the real, is intelligible, thinkable, or
knowable. By admitting, as the professor does, that the
unreal is knowable, it made philosophy in principle an
unreal science, and therefore no science at all, but nescience
or nihilism. That the germ of nihilism,concealed from the
first in the system, has not been so fatally developed in
Catholic schools as in others, is owing to Catholic theology,
which has restrained them, and held them practically within
the bounds of the real. But whenever and wherever the re-
straints of that theology have been thrown off or loosened, and
the system has had its free and natural development, it has
invariably developed in the direction, first, of egoism, as
with Descartes, Kant, and Fichte; and then of downright
nihilism, as in Hegel, Sir William Hamilton, and J. Stuart
Mill, however these pseudo-philosophers may have differed
on minor points among themselves. The only scientific
remedy is not, after the heterodox, in conforming our
theology to our philosophy, but in showing the conformity
of all true philosophy with Catholic theology: and it is for
attempting to do this, which necessitates a more or less severe
criticism on the system in which is concealed the germ of
the evil, that we are denounced as a rash innovator, or as
an Ishmaelite. We hope we shall be forgiven, if we say to
our critics,
There are more things in heaven and earth, gentlemen,
than are dreamt of in your philosophy.
Our sole aim in our philosophical essays is to show that
between true philosophy and Catholic theology there is no
discrepancy; it is only a false or defective philosophy with
no scientific value, that ever comes in conflict with the
principles of Catholic theology. Yet we find ourselves
opposed by men who do not blush to deny, as philosophers,
principles which they do and must assert as theologians.
We cannot sympathize, and never could, with this sort of
dualism; and therefore we are counted eccentric, one who
is always running to one extreme or another, never contented
to walk in a beaten path, or to keep the middle way; that is,
who is never contented to be a routinist.
Now, as the principles of science and the principles of
things are identical, it follows necessarily that we do and
can know only the real: things only as they are, only in the
order and the relation in which they actually exist. They
actually exist only in and by real and necessary being, through
its creative act. Then it is only by and in real and necessary
being,-ens necessarium et reale, and through its creative act,
not in or by themselves, that they are or can be known, are or
can be objects of science. But as things exist only in and by
being, mediante its creative act, they can be known or be in-
telligible only in the intuition of being, mediante the same act:
otherwise the principles of science and the princeples of things
would not be identical, and we should be obliged either to
deny all knowledge, or to hold that we can know without
knowing anything, as we charge that Professor Hill's system
requires us to do. As things exist, not by their own act,
but by the creative act of being, so, the principles of science
and by the principles of things being identical, they cannot be
known by their act, but only, as they exist, mediante the
creative act of being. The creative act is as necessary to the
fact of science as it is to the fact of existence,- the existence
of things, we mean. There is and can be no fact of science
or knowledge without the presentation or affirmation of being,
by its own act, as the object and light of the created intelli-
gence; and this presentation or affirmation, called self-evi-
dence, which is wholly independent of our intelligence, which
does and must precede our activity, or what we call empirical
intuition, or direct and immediate perception or apprehension,
creates and constitutes the human intellect. As the fact of
science is impossible without it, since without it there is and
can be no intelligen or knowing subject, there is and can be
no fact of science or knowledge but mediante the creative
activity fo the object, or the direct and immediate creative
act of real and necessary being affirming itself.
Now, we feel quite sure that the writer in the Pilot, who
seems disposed to make out that we misrepresent Fr.
Hill, and that on the points on which we object to his
philosophy he holds with us,- we feel quite sure, we say,
that he will not even pretend that Fr. Hill or his school
holds and teaches the doctrine we here set forth. It is the
doctrine which, as we understand it, stands opposed to the
whole modern peripatetic school, as defended by Curci,
Liberatore, Tongiorgi, San Severino, Kleutgen, Dr. Ward,
and others, and of which we have discovered no trace in
the professor's "Elements," his Logic, or his Ontology. His
definitions not only do not include, but exclude it, if we
understand them and ourselves.
The school the professor represents, and ably represents,
we are well aware, teaches that the object in the fact of
thought is ens, that is, some ens, but it may be either ens
reale, or ens possibile; but Professor Koop, we repeat, has,
in our own pages, proved that the possible is nothing in
itself, and is cognizable or thinkable only in the power or
ability of the real. Fr. Hill, and his defender in the
Boston Pilot, would do well to read Professor Koop's dis-
cussion of possibilities and the Mundus Logicus,-a priest
who cannot be accused of being too ignorant of Latin either
to understand a work written in English, or to be familiar
with the technicalities of St. Thomas and other scholastics.
Ens possibile is not a real entity, but an abstraction like
the ens in genere, and therefore created by the human mind,
and, consequently, not its object. Moreover, the ens the
school asserts, as the object of intuition, or "a term of the first
intention," does not, by its own activity, present or affirm
itself, but is simply apprehended by the direct act of the
subject. The intuition that affirms the object is the act of
the subject, not the act of the object or ens affirming itself,
and is, therefore, no surety that it is not, as some of our
German philosophers say, "subject-object," or that it is
"object-object." Kant, who shows, in his "Critik der
reinen Vernunft," that it is impossible by the most rigid
analysis of reason to refute the skepticism of Hume, makes
as do we, the fact of thought the product of subject and
object; and yet he includes the object in the subject, making
it not object-object, but a form of the intellect, therefore
subjective, or subject- object, as, without knowing it, does Fr.
Hill himself in his definition of what he calls a real term.
His " really possible," if it means anything, means the subject-
object, or object -subject fo the German school founded by
the Konigsberg philosopher.
Fr. Rothenflue, indeed, teaches that the ens, which is
the the direct and immediate object of the mind, is ens reale, and
so do Peres Fournier and Martin, all Jesuit Fathers; but their
philosophy is not approved by the Society, and its professors
are forbidden by its genersl to teach it. But Fr. Rothen-
flue did not teach the philosophy which we oppose to Fr.
Hill's school. He makes ens the object, and holds it to be
intuitively apprehended; but the intuition he asserts is the
act of the mind by its own force apprehending ens, not, as we
do, the act of ens presenting or affirming itself immediately,
and by its immediate creative act rendering the subject
intelligent, and capable of apprehending it, and, by its un-
derived light, all things dependent on its creative act that
fall within the range of our natural faculties when fully
formed and duly exerted.
There are several points here which we do not accept, or
which are not in accordance with the philosophy we defend.
Ens necessarium et reale, real and necessary being, is God in-
deed, though we do not know it by immediate intuition. Being
in the intuitive act does not affirm itself as God, but as idea;
yet it is so, for the ideal is real, and the ens intuitively affirmed,
though idea, is really God as the intelligible, or as facing
our intelligence, as we have shown in our "Refutation of
Atheism." But to maintain that we have direct and
immediate intuition of God, understanding by intuition the
act of the mind, that is direct perception, or, as we call it,
empirical intuition, as distinguished from ideal intuition,
which is the creative act of ens, or the object, is to fall into one
of the errors of the Louvain professors, and of the Sulpician,
M. Branchereau, reprobated by the Holy See. We have
intuition of ens only mediante its creative act, as it in that
act affirms, evidences itself.
Fr. Rothenflue makes ens the principle of science and of
things, which necessarily implies pantheism, as it would make
both science and things identical with real and necessary
being or God. We maintain that the principle of sience
and of things is God and his creative act. All things,
the universe and all its contents, are said to be in God eternally,
but they are so only in the sense that their types or exem-
plary ideas are in him, eternal in his essence; but these ideas,
or types, are indistinguishable from the divine essence itself,
and the assertion, that they are eternal in him, only means
that he has eternally the power to create things, existences,
the universe, the heavens and the earth, and all things therein.
They are identical with his creative power, and their asser-
tion is simply the assertion that his creative power is an
intelligent, not a blind force. We cannot, by any possible
logic, from the judgment, God is, conclude, therefore, things
or creatures are, for God is a free creator, and obliged,
neither by extrinsic force nor internal necessity, to create or
exercise his power ad extra. These ideas or types belong, if
you will, to the Divine Intelligence, but they are no element
in the created existence. There is a world of speculation
and endless distinctions on this point among schoolmen, all of
which proceed on the assumption that possibles are not
nothing in themselves, but in some sense real; and which
serve only to confuse the mind, to obscure the simple truth, and
to render metaphysics an unintelligible and even a repul-
sive science. Rational science, that is, philosophy, treats
of being only as the intelligible; it does not penetrate its
essence, and undertake to tell us what it is in itself. For the
same reason that things, creatures, contingent existences, are
not deducible from the jugment, being or God is, science
cannot be logically developed or derived from the intuition
of being alone. From the intuition of being you can only
conclude, being is, for being is eternal, self-sufficing, and
needs only itself in order to be. The intuition of being of
itself alone is not and cannot therefore be the principle of
science. Hence the condemnation of ontologism, which is
very generally supposed to be the philosophy we defend, but
is not, and never has been.
The intuition or affirmation, in order to present the prin-
ciples either of science or things, must be of both ens and
its creative act. The princeple of philosophy or rational
science, Prefessor Rossi, of Genoa, says truly, in his profound
and remarkable work, "principii di Filosofia Sopran-
naturale," is "L'ENTE CREA L'ESISTENTE," for things proceed
from being and exist only by its creative act, and, as the same
professor also says, " are not intelligible in themselves, for
they have not their reason or cause in themselves, and the
intelligibleness of a thing is in its reason or cause." This
follows from the doctrine that the principles of science and
the princeples of things are identical, for only the the real is
knowable: as we have shown over and over again, Professor
Hill and his school to the contrary not withstanding.
Science, or knowledge, is either intuitive or discursive,
direct or reflex; in the professor's terminology, either of "the
first intention," or of "the second intention." The professor,
of course, uderstands that in what he calls "the second inten-
tion," or discursive knowledge, first principles are necessary;
and, if we understand him, the principle here, that is, the
principle of demonstration, is the principle of contradiction,
which is the common doctrine of his school. We will not
stop now to examine this principle, if principle it be, for
it is of the second intention, of reflection, reasoning, or
ratiocination, and presupposes " the first intention," or
direct and immediate knowledge, apprehension, or perception,
which we call empirical intuition, in order to distinguish it
from ideal intuition, which is the act of the object, not of the
subject. Now in this intuitive order, or this direct order of
knowledge or science, we find in the professor's system no
recognition of principles, nor of any necessity of prin-
ciples. He asserts, indeed, the necessity of an objcet real or
possible, but would seem to hold that the mind, in and of
itself, by its own native intelligence, is able to apprehend and
know the object. Yet it is precisely here that our quarrel
with his system begins, or that lies the question between his
philosophy and that which we have the honor to defend. We
maintain that first or a-priori principles, principles neither
furnished by the subject from its own forms or resources, nor
obtained or obtainalble by its own act, - since without them it
cannot act at all,- are necessay, and the principal matter of
the higher philosophy. The professor, as well as his zealous
defender in the Boston Pilot, seems to be either ignorant of the
question, or to ignore it. He appears never to have understood
the difficulties in the way of human knowledge suggested by
Hume in his "Treatise on Human Nature," and which Kant
shows unanswerably, in his "Critik der reinen Vernunft,"
no analysis of reason can solve. He seems to proceed as if
the subject is itself alone competent to apprehend the real
or possible object, and that in the fact of direct knowledge or
perception it needs nothing, no principle or principles not
inherent in itself. He demands nothing from the activity of
the object, and assumes that its own subjective activity alone
suffices, Hence we charged his system with maintaining
that man, a dependent existence, is an independent intelli-
gence: which is simply absurd.
We think we have here stated the question so clearly and
distinctly, that even our modern peripatetics, however wedded
to routine, or blinded by prejudice, cannot misapprehend it.
The question, then, turns on the necessity to the fact of know-
ledge, intuitive or discursive, of a- priori principles, or, as
Kant calls them, cognitions or synthetic judgments a priori,-
judgments which precede experience, and which are not
and cannot be furnished or obtained by the action of the
subject, because, as we hold, the subject cannot act without
them. They are given by the objcet in affirming itself by its
own activity, in which the subject has no more lot or part
than he has in the divine creative act which calls him
from nothing into existence. The object is ens necessarium
et reale, real and necessary being; and it is its creative act
that gives the mind, as we have so often explained, the prin-
ciples of science, which are at the same time the principles
of all the knowable and of all the real, These principles
constitute what Gioberti names " the ideal formula," and
"I' Ente crea I' esistenze," as he tells us; Professor Rossi says:
"La formula razionale-I' Ente crea I'esistente-e il principio
primo e supremo della filosofia."
These principles, we have time and again proved, are: Real
and necessary Being creates existences; and we need not here
argue the question anew. In spite of the sneer of the writer
in the Boston Pilot, we think it sufficient to refer to our essay
in " Refutation of Atheism," already published in the
Review.
But we are gravely told that this formula, Ens creat
existentias, is ontologism, and ontologism condemned by the
Holy See. We are so told, we presume, because it is easier to
attack our philosophy than ir is to defend Fr. Hill's system.
That ontologism, as held a few years since by the Louvain
professors and several eminent fathers of the Society of
Jesus, has been pronounced by the Holy See a doctrine
that cannot be " safely taught," is well known; but that the
formula we defend falls under that or any other censure
pronounced by the Holy See, is so far as we are informed, a
very great mistake. It may, for aught we know, have been
censured by the general of the Jesuits, but not, so far as known
to us, by the Successor of Peter and Vicar of Christ. Then,
to accuse the formula of the error of the the ontologists betrays
either great hardihood or gross ignorance. We have shown the
broad difference between it and ontologism, in criticizing Fr.
Rothenflue's system. Ontologism teaches that being simply is
the principle both of science and of things, that all science is
deducible from the empirical intuition of being, and that,
given being, all existences and all science are given; while the
philosophy we defend teaches that science and existences are
derived from being, real and necessary being, indeed, but
mediante the creative act of being,- Ens creat existentias.
He who can see no essential difference between this formula
and ontologism, has no reason to applaud himself for his
intellectual acumen or powers of discrimination.
The formula we are told again, and with equal gravity, is
pantheistic. Pantheism denies the creative act, and makes
the universe and its contents, or existences, emanations, modes,
affections or phenomena of eing, or the one only substance,
Power, or Something which ir calls God, but which the
cosmists say may just as well be called nature. Now, what
are we to think of the philosopher who can discern no differ-
ence between this really atheistic doctrine, and the formula
which asserts the creative act as the copula or nexus between
being and existences, and therefore asserts that there is and
can be neither human science nor contingent existences, but
mediante the creative act of being? Why, such a philosopher
would be apt to find pantheism in the first verse of Genesis:
" In principio, Deus creavit celum et terram." But we are
told once more, and with a triumphant air not a little provok-
ing, that the human mind is not equal to the intuition of the
formula. Well, who says ir is? Have we not objected to
Fr. Rothenflue that he makes real and necessary being
perceptible by the direct and immediat act of the subject?
Do you not know, Mr. Objector, that we maintain that the
intuition which presents or affirms the formula, is the act
of being itself, not of the human mind, that it precedes it,
and that without it there is and can be no act of human
intelligence? Do, pray, read our essay in "Refutation of
Atheism," instead of dismissing it with a supercilious sneer.
You may possibly learn from it what is the philosophy we
hold, and be able to object to it with some pertinency.
Still it is insisted that, although the formula is presented or
affirmed by being itself, yet it, when so presented or affirmed,
must be received, and therefore apprehended by the subject,
otherwise the affirmation would be as if it were not. So the
objection, though removed a step, is not solved. As the being
affirmed is really the Divine Being, or God himself, it follows
that, if the subject really apprehends the formula, he really sees
God, while the Scriptures declare that "no man can see God
and live." This states the objection in its most formidable
shape. The objection has two parts: 1. The objective
intuition does not supersede the necessity of the subjective
intuition. 2. The subjective intuition, apprehension, or re-
ception of the objective intuition implies that the subject
really sees God.
1. In answer to the first part we remark that we have, as
every theologian knows, a nearly parallel difficulty with
regard to grace. Grace is not efficient unless we will to
comply with it, and we cannot will to comply with grace
without the aid of grace. The difficulty is solved by the
fact that when what if termed gratia preveniens strikes and
excites the will, it becomes itself, if not resisted, immediately
gratia adjuvans, and assists the will to comply with grace,
and when complied with, it becomes, ipso facto, gratia efficax:
that is, the three graces are simply three offices of one and
the same grace. Being does not by its objective act merely
affirm the formula, but it by its creative act gives the subject
the power or ability to receive or apprehend it:-" There is
a spirit in man, and the inspiration of the Almighty giveth
him understanding." It is as true in the natural order as in
the supernatural, what our Lord says, "Without me ye can
do nothing." It is the creative act of God, without which
we are nothing, and can do nothing: which is the copula that
binds the subjective or human judgment to the objective or
divine judgment, I Ente crea I esistenze.
2. The word see, in the second part, is ambiguous. The
Scriptures cannot mean that a man cannot know God and
live, for they everywhere teach that we do know and ought
to know God; and the condemnation of the heathen, accord-
ing to St. Paul, was, that, when they knew God, they did
not worship him as God. He declares them without excuse;
" For the invisible things of God, even his eternal power and
Godhead, have been, from the creation of the world, clearly
seen, being understood by the things that are made." (Rom. i.)
When, then, the Scriptures say no man can see God, we must
understand, not that no man can know God, or the things
of God, but that no man in this life can see God with his
bodily eyes.
Moreover, those who see so many horrible errors in the
formula, would do well to pay a little attention to what its as-
sertors mean by it. When we assert that Being, that is, God,
if you will, is affirmed intuitively to us; that w do not mean
that we see Being by our organof sense, or that we see or
know what Being is in itself, or in its essence,- which is the
intuitive vision of the blessed, and possible only by the Iumen
glorice, or the ens supernaturale, - we call the formula ideal,
and understand by the idea, not ens, or God in himself, but as
the intelligible, or as he faces the human intellect. That we
have intuition of the idea is undeniable; but the modern peri-
patetics appear never to dream of its identity with real and
necessary being, but relegate it to "the second intention,"
and lodge it in the mundus logicus, a sort of intermediary world
between the real and the unnreal, being and not-being. Yet
such an intermediary world, or mundus logicus, as dis-
tinguishable from the mundus physicus, or real world, is what
Fr. Hill's friends, the schoolmen, technically call ens rationis,
that is, fiction, nothing at all. This is what Professor Koop,
as high an authority, to say the least, as Professor Hill, has
so successfully maintained in the Review, both for April and
for July last. Besides, we ourselves did as much in our
former article on professor Hill's philosophy, and in addition
proved the reality of the ideal, or what philosophers term
"absolute ideas," "necessary ideas," as the universal, the
necessary, the immutable, the eternal, etc., without which
there is and can be no logical conclusion, no fact of experience
or cognition. These can be real only inasmuch as they are
being, real and necessary being, as we have proved over
and over, till our patience is nearly exhausted. We certainly
have, in all our mental operations, intuition of them, and con-
sequently intuition of real and necessary being; and as
all intuition is, mediante the creative act of being, we have,
in the intuition of the ideal, intuition of the formula, as the
principium both of science and of reality.
Professor Hill cannot, with Herbert Spencer, relegate God
to the dark regions of the unknowable. He holds, as we
do, that God is knowable and known, but his existence he
ranges as a term of " the second intention," that is, a con-
clusion drawn from the term of the first intention. God,
he holds, is not affirmed in direct apprehension, that is,
as we understand it, not an affirmation of direct knowledge
or intuition, but is an affirmation of reflex knowledge. If
this means that the intuition does not expressly affirm that
this is God, we accept it in the sense already explained;
but if it mean that the intuition does not directly affirm
that which is God, to wit, the ideal, or ens necessarium et
reale, we cannot, for reasons already given, accept it.
We do not question the sincerity and reality of Father
Hill's theism, any more than we do the sincerity and reality
of his Catholic faith; but the God his system asserts is,
to our understanding, only a generalization, an abstrac-
tion, and therefore no God, nor real being at all; for, if we
understand his definition, all terms of the second intention
are concepts of the reflex order, and are generalizations, or
abstractions formed by the mind operating on concretes
expressed by terms of the first intention, or as, in our
ignorance of the Latin technicalities of the schoolmen, we
say, given in intuition.
Professor Hill's system rejects the doctrine, that we have
direct intuition of real and necessary being even as the ideal,
and his ontology is derived from the apprehension or
direct knowledge of contingent existences. It is from the
intuition of contingects that he concludes the cecessay,
and from the intuition of creatures that he concludes the
necessity and the fact of the creator: as from effects we con-
clude the cause. We need not develop the argument, for
everybody knows it, and wonders at its inefficiency in con-
vincing the atheist. The existence of an effect supposes a
cause; of creature, supposes a creator; of the contingent,
supposes the necessary. Of this there is and can be no doubt.
No atheist even disputes it. But this is not the question.
The real question is, Are contingent existences intelligible
or cognizable in themselves or by themselves alone?
If congtingents can be known in or by themselves alone,
we wish the professor would tell us how from intuition of
them he can conclude the necessay, or why the necessary
is requisite to explain their existence. If the effect, in
and by itself, is intelligible, intuition or knowledge of it can
furnish no indication that it cannot exist in and of itself-can
suggest neither the fact nor the necessity of cause of reason
of its existence beyond itself. It is because effects are unintel-
ligible in and by themselves, that we conclude they are
caused; it is because they are inconceivable without something
that has caused them, that we infer from them a creator.
Besides, cause and effect, necessary and contingent, creator and
creature, are correlative terms, and correlative terms connote
each other; so that the one is never known or intelligible
without intuition of the other. The one does not simply
imply, it connotes the other, so that both are cognized in
one and the same cognition.
St. Thomas says, indeed, that God is not demonstrable from
first principles, or by an argument from cause to effect,
but from the effect to the cause; and the five different
arguments he gives, or different methods of demonstrating
that God is, all conclude the cause from the effect: which is
unobjectionable, if the mind is understood to be simultaneously
in possession of the idea of cause affirmed in the intuition of
the creative act of being as expressed in the ideal formula.
But, suppose the mind destitute of the intuition of the creative
act, or of the idea of cause, the effect could not furnish any
data from which to conclude it, because without it nothing
can be pronounced an effect, since effect is the correlative
of cause, and is intelligible only in its relation to cause, that
is, in its relation as an effect, the only sense in which it im-
plies or connotes the cause. St. Thomas always assumes that
the mind is in possesssion of the idea of cause, which he holds
to be a first principle without which no demonstration is
possible. We think Professor Hill by a more careful exami-
nation will be satisfied that the principle of demonstration is
not the principle of contradiction, which is passive and
negative, but the principle of causality, which is intuitively
supplied by the creative act of being, and of which it is
the type.
But we repeat that what is not is not intelligible. What is
not is nothing; and nothing, with all deference to the able
and learned editor-in chief of The Catholic World, cannot be
even an object of thought, therefore not intelligible, for in-
telligibleness is in being, not in not-being. Hence we main-
tain that science is of the real, not of the unreal; that the
principles of science and the principles of things of reality
are identical. Therefore, as we have already said and shown,
things must be known, if known at all, as they really exist,
and in their real relations. Creatures, contingent existences,
do not exist in themselves. "Le realta contingenti non sono
per se intelligibili, ma soltanto in virtu dell' idea eterna,"
says Professor Rossi, C.M., who adds in a note: "Se il con-
thingente non ha in se la ragione della sua esistenza non e per
se intelligibile; perche I'intelligibilita d'una cosa giace nella
sua ragione." (Ib., Art. viii, No. 251.) The induction or
demonstration of the Divine Being from contingent existences,
if we deny the ideal formula, concludes nothing, and the God
demonstrated is only a generalization, and no real or con-
crete being. Concede the formula, or the intuition, by the
object or idea, of the formula, Ens creat existentias, the
demonstration is complete. But Professor Hill's system
denies this intuition, which St. Thomas does not, though he
may not distinctly assert it; and in so far nullifies his only
demonstration of the Divine Being.
Professor Hill, if he understands himself, must accept the
doctrine of the Genovese philosopher and theologian, that
contingents are not intelligible per se, for he says, p. 149:
"Error is refuted and truth demonstrated only by principles
that are known per se, i. e., are self-evident, necessary, and
immutable." Principles which are self-evident are principles
which evidence, that is, affirm themselves: precisely what we
ourselves assert of the ideal formula. Now, how can that which
does not exist per se, has not the principle of its existence in
itself, be self-evident, or evidence itself per se? Contingents
have not the principle of their existence in themselves, do not
exist per se. How, then, can they be intelligible per se, or be
known except by virtue of the self-evident, necessary and
immutable principles, that is, again, which evidence or
affirm themselves; that is, again, which are given intuitively
by ens, the light and object of the intellect? These principles
are evidently not in contigent existence, for they are nec-
essary and immutable; yet without them truth cannot be
demonstrated: them it is impossible to demonstrate the Divine
Being without the intition of principles not contained in
contingents, not furnished by them, and without which they
themselves are unintelligible?
Thus far we have ake but little progress in the critical
examination of professor Hill's "Elements of Philosophy,"
for, contrary to our wont, we have suffered ourselves to be
put in great measure on our defence, and have, to no
little extent, been engaged in explaining and vindicating the
philosophy we oppose to the school he defends. We own
that in this we have been diverted from our oniginal design,
and have, in consequence, been obliged to go over much
ground which we had previously traversed, and to repeat
explanations and proofs of which we were already weary.
Nobody, till instructed by experience, can conceive how
hard it is to get the mind of a thorough-bred schoolman,
accustomed to the subtile distinctions, sub-distinctions, and
abstractions of the schools, out of its grooves, and to induce
him to look at things in the simple light of common-sense.
Why, we had to labor for hours with a professor of philo-
sophy to a post-graduate class in a renowned college, to
get him to admit the truism, "Nothing is nothing," and did
not succeed even at last. The most we could get from him
was, "That depends on the sense in which you use the word
nothing." He seemed very much inclined to maintain that
nothing is something! He was disposed to refine on the
word, and could not see that the assertion, nothing is nothing
is the English equivalent of the Latin assertion, "Nihil
est nihil." We spent half a day in the vain effort to
prove that the ideal formula, Ens creat existentias, is not
pantheistic; another half day, also in vain, in trying to
prove to him that there is an essential difference between the
synthetic philosophy we hold and the ontologism reprobated
by the Holy See. When once routine philosophers get the
idea in their heads that one not of their class holds such or
such a doctrine, although his system in no sense favors it,
it is next to impossible, if a doctrine not generally received
in the schools, to get it out, and to convince him of his
error and the injustice he does to his neighbor. It is this
dulness of apprehension, on the part of philosophers, in
respect of systems not strictly accordant with their own,
their nearly total incapacity to do justice to doctrines which
differ from those in which they have been trained, that
forces us to repeat our views and explanations to satiety.
We cannot divest ourselves of the hope, proved vain by
bitter experience, that at last we may hit upon some form of
statement that will prove successful. The schoolmen,
professors, and teachers of ancient Greece were called
sophists, a word originally of noble import, and naming a
most honorable and useful class, for sophist meant a sage;
but Socrates and Plato found them the bitterest enemies of
real science, and the greatest obstacles to scientific progress.
The class, though the term has become a term of contempt,
remains, and retains all its old instincts and pettifogging
spirit. We sometimes, in our moments of impatience, wish
that a new Socrates or Plato might arise, to cover, by keen
wit and polished irony, our modern sophists with ridicule.
But this is only momentary, when we have under our eyes
some newspaper article on Brownson's Philosophy. But
enough, and too much, of this.